Wednesday, December 24, 2008
Tuesday, December 02, 2008
Does Analects 12.1 Really Say Anything About Human Nature?
Bryan Van Norden seems to suggest (on p. 127 in his "Virtue Ethics and Consequentialism in Early Chinese Philosophy") that Analects 12.1 presents us with a view of human nature relatively close to Xunzi's. Although Van Norden is careful to make clear that he thinks there is no worked out conception of human nature in the Analects, he does seem to think that 12.1 offers some hint that Confucius thought of humans as naturally "resistant to virtue" in something like the way Xunzi did. Although I agree with Van Norden that there is no worked out view of human nature in the Analects, and that what we can glean from the Analects seems to make Confucius closer to Xunzi on what we ought to expect from humans in general (even aside from the issue of xing 性), 12.1 doesn't seem to me to suggest any particular view of human nature. The key to this reading, I think, is the term ji 己. If we read it as simply "oneself", then it does seem to suggest a Xunzian view of human nature. But I think there is reason (which I've been attempting to polish up arguments for in the dissertation) to see ji in 12.1 not as referring to the self, but instead as referring to certain features of oneself. Zhu Xi suggests that the right way to read ji in 12.1 is as something like "selfish desires" (The jizhu commentary on the line of 12.1 in question reads: 己謂身之私欲...). I don't take quite this line, but something relatively close. "socially non-contextualized individual" might be closer to my own reading. I take ji as representing oneself as isolated individual, which is the owner of desires and other features that can belong uniquely to individuals. I take this isolated individual, however, as something less than a full person, because it is not socially contextualized. Then, the issue becomes what human nature attaches to: the isolated individual (ji) or the properly formed person (ren人)? The Analects, although it does I think make this distinction, has no answer about which of these two human nature is involved with. There are some really difficult issues surrounding this, which I've not sufficiently thought through yet. What is clear, however, is that if ji is correctly read in either my way or Zhu Xi's "selfish desire" way, then turning away from one's ji is necessary for moral development, but there is no hint as to whether humans naturally are concerned with this ji instead of with something else. What is clear from 12.1 is that either 1) people focusing on ji to the detriment of ritual was a pressing problem among Confucius' contemporaries--because if it were not, there would be no reason to mention it in giving an answer to how one achieves ren 仁.; 2) paying undue attention to one's ji was a potential or actual problem of Yan Hui's , as the response (克己復禮爲仁 "Turning away from ji and returning/adhering to ritual is ren") was given by Confucius in answer to Yan Hui's question about ren 仁 (Yan Hui was a great student, but he wasn't perfect, after all); or 3) both 1 and 2 are true. Regardless of whether 1,2, or 3 is true, however, 12.1 then does not suggest any particular view of human nature, without further information such as "not only do people these days pay too much attention to ji, but humans in general have a natural tendency to do so." 1,2,or 3 could be true, that is, due to corrupting influences in the society which got in the way (as Mencius suggested) of human nature. Any thoughts?
Monday, October 06, 2008
Dissertation Hell!
Monday, August 11, 2008
Analects 2.3--Shame, Good Government, and Dao (Part Two)
Monday, July 28, 2008
Cheng Shude: An Early Birthday Gift, and Taking A Stand...
Wednesday, July 23, 2008
Analects 2.3--Shame, Good Government, and Dao (Part One)
Tuesday, July 22, 2008
Prepare To Be Beaten, Dead Horse!
Saturday, June 28, 2008
Phronimos, We Hardly Knew Ye
Friday, June 06, 2008
Does He Really Know Where the Ford Is?
Tuesday, April 22, 2008
Cross-Cultural Art and Confucianism
Monday, April 21, 2008
Yi (義) Can't Make a Junzi--Analects 17.23
Saturday, April 19, 2008
What Really Matters--Analects 13.18
Wednesday, April 09, 2008
Are We Arguing Past Each Other?
Wednesday, April 02, 2008
Problematic Arguments To Link Confucius and Aristotle
Thursday, March 27, 2008
Listening to the Past
Saturday, March 22, 2008
The "Al Qaeda Effect" and Why We Don't Care About the Uighurs
Sunday, February 24, 2008
A Matter of Efficacy
So--I've been thinking recently about a question that seems to continually arise when I present my work on Confucianism to philosophers working outside of Chinese philosophy. The question is: to what extent for Confucians (as represented by the Analects, at least) is the use of force acceptable as a means of ensuring communal agreement and the correct ordering of the social hierarchy? Variations of this question, I have noticed, always come up when I present to non-specialists, and hardly ever come up when I present to specialists. In fact, when I was first confronted with this question, I had to respond that I hadn't given it much thought myself, even though I spend a whole lot of time thinking about early Confucianism.
So, two questions occur to me now: 1) why do non-specialists tend to worry about the issue mentioned above more than specialists? 2) what is Confucius' view on the use of force? I think that both of these questions can be answered by looking not to the Analects, however, but to the Daodejing, which shares certain features with Confucian literature (even the Analects!), and offers better explanations of some processes discussed in the Confucian as well as the Daoist literature.
The passage of the DDJ that seems relevant here (as well as my favorite DDJ passage) is DDJ 17 (Lau trans.):
"The best of all rulers is but a shadowy presence to his subjects. Next comes the ruler they love and praise; next comes the one they fear; next comes the one with whom they take liberties. When there is not enough faith, there is lack of good faith. Hesitant, he does not utter words lightly. When his task is accomplished and his work done, the people all say, 'it happened to us naturally.'"
For the daoist, like the Confucian, the use of force to attain order (or one's goals, whatever they are) is acceptable, but a sign that one is doing something wrong. A ruler who needs to resort to force has failed in a fundamental way. This, of course, is not because it is somehow wrong to use force--arguably the classical Chinese tradition in general did not see violence as intrinsically an evil, as does (for the most part) the post-Christianity western tradition. Rather, the reason using force is not as good as other methods is, as DDJ 17 suggests, a matter of efficacy, with which the Chinese tradition is deeply concerned.
DDJ 17 suggests that the "shadowy presence" is the best kind of ruler because this ruler is the one who will be able to impose his will on the people without their even knowing it. Why, we might ask, is this situation the best one for a ruler to be in? To take a strictly Machiavellian (or Legalist, for that matter) line here, the "shadowy presence" will be, of the four types of ruler, the one whose power is most secure. Think of this in terms of likelihood of rebellion and overthrow. The "shadowy presence" cannot be rebelled against or overthrown, because his will is invisible. The people do his will seemingly of their own will, so the only ones they have to rebel against if they disapprove of what they must do is themselves! The ruler who is loved is not quite as stable in his power. He has some stability, however, because the people are unlikely to rebel against and overthrow this ruler. Their love for him keeps him in power, and the people will not go against their ruler even when the opportunity arises. The ruler who is feared and imposes his will by force (this is where the "justifiability of force" question comes to play) is less secure than either the "shadowy presence" or the ruler who is loved, because even though he can keep order while he has strength, if the opportunity arises or if the ruler's strength diminishes, the people will quickly rebel and overthrow this ruler. Thus, his power is based on volatile external situations--there is much that is simply out of his control, and thus his hold on power is less secure. The ruler with whom the people take liberties, of course, is doomed, because he does not even have the fear of the people to rely on. They do not respect his will, and are likely to subvert it whenever they feel like it. This kind of ruler is a ruler in name only, and has no control over his people.
It is not only in terms of holding power that we can read DDJ 17, however. It will also be true that the better types of rulers will be more effective at making a virtuous society, etc. Just like much of the DDJ, 17 does not offer us normative claims about ends, but about means. The DDJ offers us a method, whereas the Confucian and Mohist texts give us a picture of the ends we ought to be aiming to achieve. The Daoist concern with method rather than ends, however, does not mean that its methods are all that different from those of the Confucian, and on this issue (rulership), they seem to line up nicely. What is the "shadowy presence" of DDJ 17, after all, if not the sagely ruler of Analects 2.1 who, like the pole star, simply "facing south" creates virtue through the de around which the people gravitate?
So, this is the beginning of an answer to question 2 above, I think. What about question 1? That is--why do non-specialists focus on the question of whether force is justified in Confucianism as a way to realize the goals of the community? I suspect that one of the reasons for this is that the notion of the rulership in the western tradition has developed in a somewhat different way than in the Chinese tradition. The "shadowy presence" has not been seen as the ideal of rulership in much of western history (there are, of course, exceptions, including Machiavelli). Rather, the "loved and praised" ruler whose power is on full display has been the ideal for much of western history (Alexander the Great, Charlemagne, etc.). The benevolent and powerful king whose commands are direct and clear for the world to see but who is well loved--this has been the western ideal. The noble Homeric warrior, storming the front lines of the enemy's army, rather than the ninja in the shadows or the sniper blending in with concrete and raining silent death from above, has been the western ideal. Thus, perhaps resorting to force to control a community is seen as a "plan B" in this tradition, whereas it is less justified in the Chinese tradition, being a measly "plan C". This, along with the fact that violence in itself is not seen as intrinsically evil in Chinese thought, as it is in much of western (post-Christian) thought, may help to explain why the "force question" arises more among non-specialists in Chinese philosophy than it does among specialists. Of course, I'm not completely comfortable with this answer, but I'll need to reflect on this some more to come up with something better. Any thoughts?